"A Wrong,
Not a Right: An Atheist Libertarian Looks at
Abortion" was published in Rampart Individualist, Vol. 1,
No. 4, Fall 1983, as part of "Abortion: Two Libertarians
Debate the Pros and Cons." Wendy McElroy wrote the opposing
view, in "What Does It Mean to Be an Individual? Self-Ownership Is Key to Abortion
Issue" -- a version of which can be found on
Wendy McElroy's Web site under the title,
"Abortion."
Slightly different versions of "A Wrong, Not a Right" were
published in Nomos, Summer 1983, and Foretell,
1993.
On January 22, 1973, the Supreme Court in effect legalized
abortion on demand until birth. On January 23, 1983, in an
article marking the tenth anniversary of the decision, The
Washington Post said, "To this day, many [legal experts
such as John Hart Ely] who fully approve of the result seem
uncomfortable" with the court's reasoning. As this
prominent scholar wrote in the Yale Law Journal, said the
Post, this decision was "'frightening... It is not
constitutional law and gives almost no sense of an
obligation to try to be.' The court 'simply announces' a
right to abortion."
Even if abortion were constitutional, it shouldn't be. For
abortion is not merely contraception or termination of
pregnancy; it is prenatal infanticide. Nothing in science
or philosophy supports this killing.
When does human life begin?
When abortion is not the issue, even pro-abortionists agree
on the biological facts. Babies are not made in heaven and
then delivered at birth by storks; they arrive in this world
at conception. Life comes from life, but the individual
existence of each human being has its own starting point.
Neither sperm nor ovum is a separate creature of the species
Homo sapiens -- but together they generate a new human
entity; individually they cease to exist at conception
(fertilization), when by fusion they produce a zygote, a
unique human being.
Each of us begins his or her existence at conception with
only one cell. This cell is special: All that which we will
become later is essentially there; for this cell has the
fundamental internal capacity to differentiate itself into
the various organs of the human body. Even at conception,
we were male or female human beings. Our hearts began to
beat by the third week. Just seven weeks after conception,
cell differentiation produced an integrated system of
tissues and organs: blood, brain, and so on. By the end of
the eighth week, all our body systems were present. As we
grew in the womb, we responded to pain, cold, taste, light,
and sound.
We developed human consciousness; woke, slept, and dreamed.
Maturity came not at birth but gradually over years. No
substantial change occurred in us by being born; birth was
just a change of physical location, eating and breathing
habits.
Some ask us to believe that the prenatal child, the fetus,
is a "thing," a non-human animal, or (at best) merely a
"potential human being." However, a fetus is an actual
human being -- with potential -- a child in fact.
("Fetus" is simply Latin for "offspring," including
offspring of non-human species. "Child" means, more
specifically, "human offspring," born or preborn.) However
much we may change throughout life, the human being we are
now is the fetus and child we were then, only older.
But are preborn children "persons"?
If human beings are persons then, prima facie, all human
beings, born and preborn, are persons, too. Biologically,
there is only one generic class of human beings: everyone
from conception until death. Bodies and minds mature and
develop, but personhood either is or isn't. Being a person
is a matter of kind, not degree; some of us are not "more of
a person" and others "less," with some of us having a
greater right not to be harmed and others less. Neither are
there two classes of human beings: "persons" and
"non-persons." This dichotomy cannot be reasonable or just,
for it's not based upon any rational explanation of what is
a person.
A "person" is a living entity with the inherent, internal
capacity to develop reason and choice. Human beings have
this potential at conception; they actualize this capacity
as they develop. Being a person is not determined by what
we are at any given moment but by what we are and shall be
throughout life.
A human being is not a static thing but a changing entity.
A human life is a spectrum of development, manifesting
different abilities and achievements over time, all of which
are the evolutionary products of the same individual that
came into existence at conception. Selecting as the
standard of personhood a test that focuses on a single
development in this spectrum, or on a single manifestation
of the evolving abilities that humans possess as a
consequence of their genetic makeup, is merely arbitrary.
A particular test may be objective regarding the specific
physical characteristic being measured (e.g., brain waves or
"viability"), but this does not necessarily make it an
objective test of personhood as a whole. No single line in
the spectrum of human life sufficiently represents what life
is, in all its complexity, to serve as the standard for
conferring, or denying, the most important of human
attributes: individual rights.
There is only one objective, non-manipulable test for
personhood: having come into existence at conception as a
human being. Human beings don't become persons; human
beings are persons. Our human nature on which our rights
rest is acquired immediately and irrevocably at conception,
when we acquire our human genes. To deny this basic fact of
genetics is to subject our natural rights to the arbitrary
opinions of others, after as well as before birth. Whatever
the intent, the effect of this denial is that only might
makes right and the concept of inalienable rights becomes
meaningless.
Human life and human rights co-exist. Possessing rights is
the consequence of being alive. Even pro-abortionists admit
that rights end when an individual's life ends. It's
perfectly reasonable to hold that rights begin -- especially
the right not to be killed -- when an individual's life
itself begins at conception. Although the ability to
exercise one's rights may vary from person to person and
time to time, being a person is a constant.
If pro-abortionists could find an objective test to support
abortion, they would rally around it. Instead, they differ
radically as to what test we must pass in order to be
certified as persons. For various groups, the critical
event occurs as early as implantation to years after birth
(e.g., socialization). However, the premise implicit in
these tests -- namely, that our rights depend upon whether
or not we can demonstrate an ability or an achievement to
someone else's satisfaction -- is unlibertarian; it
endangers everyone's freedom. Requiring doctors and
plumbers to be licensed is wrong, as libertarians insist.
Imposing a "licensing" requirement for personhood is even
more offensive.
Nothing happens at birth that "magically" transforms us into
persons. If a person comes out of the womb, then one had to
be there before birth. Twins are born one at a time. Can
the first-born be a person but not the other minutes from
birth? Is killing the second twin justifiable?
If the purely biological fact of birth is what transforms
non-persons into persons, then what about non-human mammals?
No one pretends that their mere birth transforms them into
persons. Something more is both necessary and sufficient:
such as being human.
Most of us see only born people, so thinking of preborn
children as "us," especially at conception, seems strange.
Nevertheless, they look like what human beings are supposed
to look like, and what we once looked like before birth.
With technology, strangeness may turn to familiarity.
Parents, as well as doctors, can now view children in
utero with ultrasound. There are other means of observing
them: fetoscopy, amniocentesis, hysteroscopy, and electronic
fetal heart monitorinq -- all new in the last ten years
[before this article was written in 1983]. Movies about
life during gestation have been shown on television.
Doctors have operated upon preborn children in and ex
utero.
Ironically, in some hospitals, while some doctors are
struggling to save sickly preborns, other doctors are busy
killing older but healthy preborns, merely because they are
"unwanted" by their mothers. One of the dreaded
consequences of abortion is that some children survive the
procedure. May they be killed, or are they now home free?
The fact is that their rights are being ignored and they are
being killed.
But what about the woman's right to control her own
body?
It is never enough to talk about anyone's right to control
his or her own body when someone else's body and rights are
affected. But, some say, preborn children don't count.
They are not individuals but merely a "part of the woman's
body," like her heart or other organs.
Biology provides no basis for this view. Mother and child
are two individuals, for they are genetically distinct.
They are not even attached to each other at conception. A
"test-tube" baby spends the first few days in a petri dish,
far from the mother. A baby conceived naturally does not
connect to the mother at conception but [around 5-9] days
later, after floating down her Fallopian tube into her womb.
In neither situation is the preborn child a part of where he
or she lives.
Even after implantation, the child becomes isolated inside
his or her amniotic sac, and from that point on, makes
indirect contact with the mother only by way of an umbilical
cord and placenta. Siamese twins are directly attached to
each other, yet even they are two individuals.
Micro-organisms of various species live in us, but no one
claims they are biologically a part of us.
Others argue, the preborn child -- whether an individual or
part of her body -- is the mother's property. How can this
be? Property rights imply the right to retain ownership
until one chooses to relinquish it. If preborn children
were someone's property, then birth would not change their
status. Certainly, being on another person's property
doesn't make one human being the property of another, in the
sense that the owner may do whatever she will with the other
individual. The woman's physical power to control her
child, as by abortion, doesn't make the child her property
in a moral or legal sense. If it did, then states could
claim people as property, by right. But people are simply
not property, ever.
Some say abortion is a woman's right just because "it's her
body" which must supply the child's needs. But what about
after birth? Breast feeding is a natural means of providing
infants with nutrition. In societies or situations where
only breast feeding (as opposed to bottle feeding) is
available, may the mother starve her child by willfully
withholding her milk? Suppose no other milk is available?
Suppose children could be transferred from womb to womb or
to artificial wombs? Would they become persons in transit
only to become non-persons again? Might a child in an
artificial womb be regarded as a removed appendix, as the
woman's property? Or the father's property? Suppose
children could be kept there indefinitely? Might we raise
them as guinea pigs, or slaves, or for body parts? Does
being a person depend upon some outside, accidental factor
like the ability of scientists to do these things -- or upon
what we are, in ourselves, internally?
Is abortion ever permissible?
Bringing children into the world can present many
difficulties for both parents. Sometimes the strain can
seem impossible to bear. But even here we can't turn our
backs on the children in the womb.
What if the mother's life is in danger? "Lifeboat"
situations have no pat answers and are continuing problems
for philosophy. But abortion is not normally a matter of
self-preservation -- however much some pro-abortionists wish
us to believe it is. In the rare cases where it may be,
proper medical care aims (and generally succeeds) at saving
both patients. It does not kill the child on purpose, as
most abortions do.
What of mentally and physically defective children? Because
even severe imperfection is no excuse for killing born
people, it's no excuse for prenatal infanticide. Because
nobody's perfect, think of the possibilities now that we
have started down this slippery slope.
What of rape and incest? If sex is consensual, no special
consideration is needed in incest cases. There is no right
to kill third parties for what two people have chosen to do
with each other.
In rape, the situation of pregnancy is imposed upon the
woman, but so is it imposed upon the child. Although the
woman's victimization is distressing, her life is not
normally at risk. She can carry the child to term and thus
continue the rapist's aggression against herself; or she can
herself aggress against her innocent child.
But just because the rapist has harmed the mother, that
doesn't entitle the mother to harm her child. Being
victimized doesn't justify victimizing others. Taking the
child's life is a greater evil than having to carry her
child to term. Rape victims deserve our empathy and help,
but never our "permission" to kill. Once the child is born,
others may take the child if the mother wishes. That the
rapist/father has obligations to both victims, ought to need
no emphasis.
If they are "unwanted," are preborn children aggressors?
All persons have the obligation not to aggress. Therefore,
some pro-abortionists say, even assuming preborn children
are persons, they have no right to live in the mother or at
either parent's expense. Abortion is self-defense, for
unwanted children are "aggressors," "parasites," or
"trespassers." They may be evicted from the womb and
abandoned, even if death results. Parents have no more
responsibility to their own children than to children next
door or halfway around the world.
There are three errors in the pro-abortionists' position.
It ignores the fact that most abortions, as they are done
today, intentionally kill children before eviction. And,
even conceding trespass or parasitism, neither is,
justifiably, a capital offense. Finally, the fatal flaw in
the argument: Preborn children are not aggressors in any
form. As one Libertarians for Life leaflet explains:
"Aggression involves an act of will or an act of negligence.
It can never arise from an act that is caused by existential
forces beyond an individual's control... [T]here cannot be
aggression if human action, in the sense of purposeful
behavior, is not involved at all.
"The creation of the fertilized egg and its attachment to
the uterine wall are not 'acts' of the unborn child in the
sense of being purposeful. They are the result of
existential biological forces independent and beyond the
control of the child (although not of the father and the
mother), and brought into play by the combined acts of the
father and mother.
"[Because] the unborn child cannot rationally be held
responsible for its own creation, it cannot rationally be
held to have committed aggression by coming into -- indeed,
being brought into -- existence. Aggression implies
responsibility; and no human being is responsible for his
own creation.
"[As] the unborn child is not and cannot be an aggressor,
the mother cannot invoke the privilege of self-defense
against its continued existence in the one place in which,
at that stage in its development as a human being, it is
both logically and biologically appropriate for it to be."
("If the Unborn Child is a Person Entitled to Rights,
Abortion is Aggression," Edwin Vieira,
Jr.)
Children do not cause their own existence; parents cause it.
Parenthood and the obligation to prevent harm
Abortion is wrong because of the universal obligation not to
kill innocent people. Moreover, as sex is voluntary
(barring rape), parents also have the obligation to take
care of their children. The needs of parents and child may
conflict, but children have a right to this care.
Libertarians agree that one person's needs are never, in
themselves, of any compulsory obligation upon anyone else.
Therefore, some conclude, until an individual initiates
force or fraud, or violates a contract, obligations are
optional. Until someone actually causes harm, there is no
legitimate basis for compelling anyone to do anything.
But what about self-defense? We may use, or threaten to
use, appropriate compulsion at appropriate times against
anyone who causes us, without our assent, to be in harm's
way. Running the risk of harming people is not necessarily,
in itself, aggression, but intentionally or negligently
failing to prevent the harm from happening is. The
obligation to prevent harm when we put others in harm's way
is not optional.
A child's right to parental care is derived from the right
of self-defense, the right to avoid being harmed. The
choice to have sex includes the choice to risk bringing
helpless babies into the world. Although this puts children
at risk, no injustice is necessarily done. But if parents
intentionally or negligently fail to take care of their
children and harm results, they are accountable.
Life is a series of risks, but we have no right to impose
upon others the consequences of the risks we choose and then
compel them to bear the costs. Having used contraception,
or not wanting children, does not exempt parents from their
obligation to provide for them if they are conceived anyway.
Even if we do our best to reduce the risk of pregnancy, most
of us still know the risk remains. Once children are
conceived, we may not make the additional choice to harm
them years, months, weeks or even minutes later.
Dependent children are like "captives," for they are in
their parents' control. There is no general right to choose
to bring harm to innocent people in our control, especially
if we caused them to be there, and parents have no special
exemption from this principle. Taking care of our children
until they can fend for themselves is not slavery, just as
paying one's debts is not slavery. Compelling a stranger to
do so may be, but there is a big difference between being
the parent and being a stranger.
Libertarians agree that we have no compulsory obligation to
provide for someone else's children; but, if we cause them
(or anyone else) to be in harm's way, we owe them
protection. It follows that, as we are responsible for our
own children's very creation, we owe them at least as much
protection (e.g., adoption). But when we choose abortion,
not only are we denying them protection, we are making sure
they are harmed.
If we may not choose to harm other people, how can it be all
right to harm our own children, especially with violence?
It isn't, of course -- and this is why many pro-abortionists
admit they don't like abortion and fervently insist they are
not "pro-abortion," only "pro-choice." Many demand tax
funds for abortion as well, thus making it doubly clear that
by "pro-choice" they mean someone else's "no-choice." Not
only are they killing the children, they are killing the
language, too.
Conclusion
Libertarianism is strongly pro-choice, but never when there
is a victim. Rights, including the right to choose, are
limited by what justice requires: we may not choose to rob,
kill, or otherwise harm peaceful people. We must honor our
debts and agreements, return property wrongfully taken, and
pay restitution when we cause harm. And when we voluntarily
cause others to be at risk, when their part is not
voluntary, we have the obligation to prevent harm from
actually occurring. Abortion is a wrong, not a right.
Under justice, it is unthinkable.
Where there are laws, they should oppose wrongdoing, not
permit it. Some say legalizing abortion is "neutral," but
it's not. Instead, it's incredibly dangerous, for what
about the victim? Should there be a class of innocent
persons whose killing is permitted and protected by the law?
Such an idea is one that both sides of the abortion debate
should see as absolutely incompatible with individual
liberty.
if we wish to defend individual liberty, we must protest
aggression by individuals against individuals, as well as
aggression by governments against individuals. The
Libertarian Party Platform stresses defending individual
liberty against governmental intrusion. While it also
endorses "the right to life" and insists children have
rights, unfortunately it also endorses abortion on demand at
any time prior to birth. Not many governments cause well
over a million deaths yearly. Yet this is the destruction
abortion brings yearly in the United States alone. The
death toll world-wide is staggering.
As a libertarian, I am particularly concerned. Libertarians
are the leaders in the fight for individual rights. But if
we continue to take part in this terrible injustice, to
where will we lead?