In listening to the debate over abortion, I have frequently found that those on the two
sides are using are two quite different ways of thinking. To some extent, this is a matter
of "values", of "worldview". To that extent, those on both sides who
see abortion as a religious issue will find the existence of such different perspectives
as confirmation of their view.
In some
respects, however, the dichotomy does not seem to require such a global perspective. In
some respects, at least, it seems to manifest itself as a fairly narrow, relatively
definable difference in modes of thought. Just above, I used the term "ways of
thinking" -- but this usually means simply that people disagree on some topic.
Rather, people here seem to be using different structures of thought -- in brief, the two
sides have two different ways of engaging in the activity of defining.
Frankly, I have not heard very much discussion,
on either side, of these two "mechanisms of thought". Frankly, also, I rather
doubt that I shall hear much of it in the future. Nonetheless, I hope this little paper
will spark some discussion.
I take for granted that the points made here,
and whatever points are made in response, have been made elsewhere, and many times before.
But I suspect that most people who are concerned with public affairs will find the points
terribly abstract -- and only peripherally useful, at best, in understanding the debate
over abortion. The points, I'm afraid, may well remain locked securely in whatever books
and papers in which they now reside.
So, in writing this paper, I have tried to keep
things as open as possible so that readers aware of one book or article or another will
not feel constrained to silence because I was "really discussing something slightly
different".
If readers on either side of the debate are
aware of books, or articles, or writers who have confronted the dichotomy, I hope they
will let me know about them. Regardless of the larger debate over abortion, this paper
will have been a success to the extent I find others who have similarly tried to explore
the dichotomy that I see underlying at least part of the abortion controversy.
Two perspectives
At the foundation of the debate over abortion
is the debate over prenatal personhood. Pro-lifers generally affirm that the preborn are
persons from the moment of conception, from fertilization. Those who believe abortion
should be legal generally deny prenatal personhood. (If they agree that the preborn are
persons after, say, three months or six, they also usually agree that abortion can be
restricted after that point.)
Listening to the debate, two general
perspectives emerge, two ways of justifying one's conclusion on this question.
First, there are those who hold the preborn are
persons from conception. They hold that to be a person is a matter of what
"kind" of being we are; they refer to our "capacity",
"power", or "potential" for reason and choice -- and point to even the
zygote as having such a capacity. The preborn are argued to have the potential because,
given time and sustenance, they will eventually manifest it. (Pro-lifers also describe the
preborn in terms we may call "internal" -- the fetus senses heat or light at
such and such a time, hears sounds at such and such a time.) They insist the zygote is the
same kind of being as the adult, differing only in degree. And being the same kind --
however the issue is phrased -- means they are persons.
Next, there are all the others -- and
here, there can be a wide variety. Some may assert personhood relatively early -- say,
with the onset of brainwaves. Others may deny it until well after birth.
It may seem unkind or inaccurate to lump
together all these apparently disparate groups. And listening to defenders of abortion,
one frequently hears them distancing themselves from one another.
But their differences arise out of their
similarity. They all seem to be couching their position in terms that are alien to the
pro-lifers. Some use terms like the "manifestation" of rationality; some insist
upon some particular level of development before one can be called a person. Others wish
to see a particular kind of behavior. Most look for things that can be observed from the
outside.
They are all using a language of act, of
demonstration, of behavior.
Some may phrase their position in terms of
"machinery" -- the presence of the cerebral cortex, say. But this, too, seems
more a matter of act or degree -- development -- than of potential or kind. (For a bit
more on treating it as power or potential, see below, "The machinery".)
Seeing such a underlying dichotomy may seem
simplistic to many of you. For the moment, you may wish to see the dichotomy as obtaining
in its "pure" form only between the pro-lifers and those who concede personhood
only near or after birth. Alternatively, you may wish to see it as obtaining only between
the pro-lifers, on the one side, and those on the other side who disagree among themselves
over relatively fine points in development as the point at which we become persons.
But I would point out that the logic underlying
this dichotomy seems to apply equally well to discussing all the gradations in between
conception and even advanced levels of maturity. (The mere fact that those supporting
abortion do indeed take positions that are graded along time and development leads one to
suspect that the notion of degree is applicable.)
Many formulations
Underlying the debate over prenatal personhood,
then, there seem to be two different ways of "defining" what it means to be a
person. Usually, I'll refer to the dichotomy as power versus act. But, as I've noted,
there a variety of formulations possible to describe the underlying dichotomy. Among them:
power and act, kind and degree, capacity and demonstration, nature and behavior, potential
and manifestation, etc., etc., etc.
I don't think it's necessary to try to decide
which would be the best formulation of the dichotomy. Were we to do so, there might well
be significant implications of each one that would be important in certain contexts. But
relative to abortion, the dichotomy between the two sides is so great that the differences
among those on one side can be set aside for this discussion. (Personally, I think the
different formulations are merely stating different aspects of the same thing; but that's
neither here nor there.)
Two formulations I'd reject
Two pitfalls in formulation merit attention,
though.
By "potential", I don't mean
"possible".
The bricks in a brick yard are not a
"potential" house (or wall, or bridge). The most we can say is that they're a
"possible" house, etc. The acorn, shoot, or sapling, however, is a potential
full-grown tree.
Both potential and possible are contingencies:
to occur, they each require other things to be either present or absent. A good hurricane
or earthquake can take care of both bricks and tree, and a drought alone can take care of
the tree. But the tree is itself an active participant in actualizing its potential.
That's what living things do.
The zygote (and any living creature, any
biological individual) is a self-assembler. The pile of bricks is not.
Also, I don't intend a dichotomy between
"potential" and "actual".
I'm willing to go so far as a dichotomy between
"potential for x" and "actualization of x". A dichotomy between
possible and actual may be valid. But as I'm using "potential" here, the
potential for x is actual; the potential is currently existing, although the x is not. I
am talking about a power of an existing individual.
A reply to one objection
Of course, one could say that potential means
nothing more than possible; one could deny that there is any difference in reality between
the bricks and the acorn.
According to that view, all we can know is that
the bricks eventually wound up as a house (and that the brick masons took part), and that
the acorn grew into a tree (and that rain and light, etc., took part also). Why
acorns go through this so regularly, but bricks turn up in such odd associations, is not a
question that makes any sense. All we can see is events. There are no why's.
Well, the problem is that neither the universe
nor the human mind seems to be congenial to that point of view. The universe is indeed
relatively predictable, providing plenty of why's to those willing to look. And the human
mind is both willing to look and annoyed when no why's are found.
The attitude that why is meaningless may be a
convenient foil for discussion, but most of us are quite aware that it is a foil only, not
a real question.
And to another
However, for those for whom the distinction
between potential and possible is genuinely unsatisfactory, the resolution of the problem
may be quite simple. I shall simply point back to the brick yard, then to the acorn. Given
the different ways the two behave, what are the best words to use? Some have referred to
those facts of life by the labels "potential" and "possible". How
shall we more appropriately name them?
This is the same approach I would take to those
who object to formulations such as power and act or kind and degree. I am willing to
accept practically any labels so long as they serve to describe the underlying fact.
I don't mean by this to dismiss problems of
formulation as mere quibbles over word play. Rather, the task is to not to let differences
of formulation get needlessly in the way of dealing with the underlying facts.
Another formulation problem
One other problem of formulation is that the
same words may be used by both sides to describe quite different things.
For instance, supporters of abortion may deny
that the preborn have any "capacity" for reason and choice. And they may say
that the "capacity" is indeed what makes us persons. Here, though, they're using
the word in a different sense than is used by the pro-lifer. For the defender of abortion,
"capacity" seems to mean something that we can do pretty much as an act of will.
That's one way the word is frequently used. This "capacity" seems to be
the manifestation of the "capacity" to which the pro-lifer appeals. (Again, see
below, "The machinery".)
I think we should be aware of the different
uses of the same words. But I don't think it poses any problem -- the words have
those different uses: the fact that the same term is used does not usually obscure the
fact that it is used in different ways.
Some agreements
Before going further, I should note where I
think both sides in the abortion debate agree (or where their disagreements are not
material).
First, I think both sides more or less agree on
the basic practical facts: the presence or absence of brainwaves, of concept
formation, etc. Note: "more or less". They obviously disagree to some extent,
but I think those disagreements are immaterial to the basic point. When we're talking
about whether the zygote is a person, we don't need to worry about what flavor of
brainwaves appear at what week of gestation.
Also, I think both sides agree that reason and
choice is the fundamental character that makes us persons. Again, the formulations
certainly differ: reason and choice, conceptual consciousness, volitional activity,
rationality, etc. The formulations may indicate significant differences about what being a
person is, but I don't think they go so far as to impinge on questions like one's right
not to be killed absent one's initiation of any force.
Power and act
The question is how reason and choice
make us persons.
Is it a matter of a power we have? (Or a
potential, capacity, etc., etc.) Or is it a matter of an act in which we engage? (Or a
behavior, manifestation, etc., etc.)
When they defend act, I think that its
proponents would point out that they can practicably explain the data of reality without
resorting to power. Even if we concede this, however, the presence of an adequate
explanatory structure does not preclude the possibility that there are relatively better
structures. If power can remove grey areas, then it cannot be dismissed prima facie.
By defining personhood as a matter of power, we
dispense with at least most grey areas. The critical question would be whether the child
is alive. We may still have fascinating questions -- what are the implications of, say, a
catastrophic genetic defect such as the absence of a brain? (I have to wonder whether life
could be sustained in many of the sort of cases raised.) But at the minimum, we have fewer
and rarer grey areas. They are, in fact, reduced to the area of abnormalities -- we
would not need to judge between normal stages of development.
Just above, I may have seemed to concede that
one can practicably explain the data of reality without resorting to power. That, however,
is debatable. We may reasonably describe the data without recourse to power, but I
don't think we can explain it (as indicated in "Two formulations I'd
reject", above).
Why does the individual that was once a zygote
now discuss philosophy? (Thomas Aquinas, part of a world that believed that a homunculus
was present in the "seed", would simply deny that the same biological individual
was still present; I don't think that option is still open.)
It strikes me that the recognition of act
entails the recognition of power. (Of course, one may say the power is necessary, but not
sufficient for personhood. As I indicated near the very beginning, though, I haven't seen
arguments that explicitly accept the presence of the power but deny its sufficiency.)
But that brings us to another formulation of
the question of prenatal personhood: power is what distinguishes both adults and the
zygote from the lower animals; act is what distinguishes adults from zygotes; why is the
difference between zygote and adult more important than the similarity?
And the question of the lower animals seems to
cause a problem for the argument from act.
The problem of the lower animals
Most who hold to act also try to set it low
enough to concede the personhood of at least infants and frequently the late-term preborn.
But how does that square with denying personhood to the lower animals?
On any external index of
"intelligence" (problem solving, etc.), it would seem that chimpanzees and other
primates "think" more than infants. (If I recall some anthropology articles
correctly, it seems that even infant chimpanzees "think" at a more advanced
level than do human infants -- even if only for a few weeks or months.)
If act is what counts, how can we include in
the category of person those who act at a lower level than others we exclude?
The machinery
I think the response would be that at some
point "the machinery's in place" -- the cerebral cortex, etc. But if the
machinery isn't producing the output, then we are talking power again, not act. And
talking power, one has to face the fact that the power exists before the point at which
the cerebral cortex (or what not) is produced.
"The machinery's in place" in the
zygote, too -- after all, the nature of this "machinery" is to grow. And even at
birth, the machinery still has growing to do before the human infant will manifest any
superiority to a number of the lower animals.
A response?
I think one response would be to point to the
question of essence itself -- that, for example, Ayn Rand holds that essence to be an
epistemological, not a metaphysical notion of essence. I have presumably been holding to a
"metaphysical" notion of essence, of what it is to be a person. An
"epistemological" notion of essence would sidestep all difficulties.
Frankly, I can see no relation between the
epistemological/metaphysical distinction and the power/act distinction. The closest I can
come is to fall back to the idea that power just doesn't exist in concrete individuals.
Somehow I doubt that Rand intended to say she was silent on concrete individuals. As
noted, though, I haven't been able to find any straightforward confrontation -- Randian or
otherwise -- with the argument from power.
Nonetheless, I don't really see that the
metaphysical/epistemological distinction makes any difference here. We are not dealing
with a phenomenon that strikes us all as inexplicable. It's not as if rosebuds were
turning into philosophers or infants into oak trees. Nor are we dealing with something
that requires some great leap in the knowledge of mankind -- both sides agree to the data.
(Pro-lifers are not asserting that the zygote is contemplating logic.)
Agreed, the personhood of the preborn would be
a logical affront to the primacy of act. But what other problems would arise?
Are there any?
Or is it just that it's intuitively obvious
that the early preborn can't be persons? Is it that we all "just plain know"
that?
The unacceptable cost
In practical reasoning, we frequently appeal to
the idea of "unacceptable costs". Implicitly, I have done so here. In relying on
act, we are left with no principle to distinguish between infants and at least some
of the lower animals. We're caught in a bind: recognize chimpanzees as persons -- or deny
infants.
Above, I only took that to apply in the
abstract. Those who set personhood fairly early -- the appearance of cerebral cortex, say
-- may feel it doesn't apply to them. They can concede the power and demand only a very
plausible degree of manifestation. After all, we can't think without a brain, can we?
But their problem is not with someone who is
going to demand they deny personhood until the child grows up and gets a Ph.D. Nor is
their problem with someone who will ask them to recognize personhood at conception.
Rather, one they really have to answer is one
who asks them to deny personhood for a few more days or weeks -- until some other
reasonable indication of the power is available, say, production of more
"human-type" brainwaves.
Their problem is also with those who wish to
recognize personhood just a little bit earlier.
In either case, I suspect that their response
will be that they have pointed to a perfectly reasonable, plausible, perhaps even
measurable indicator of the power to reason and choose. But -- given that we're looking at
a living, growing being -- the other conditions are also reasonable, plausible, and
perhaps even measurable.
The disagreement itself is reasonable,
plausible, and perhaps even measurable.
The bottom line is that the reliance on act
precludes any principled grounds for saying no to those who set their conditions a bit
higher or a bit lower.
It is most emphatically not that they
are dishonest in their stated desire to recognize personhood at day x. It is not
that they wish to see the day put off forever. It is that they have only their own
sincerity and wishes to back up their position.
And it is quite telling that they get most
upset when it appears that their arguments will be used to justify putting off personhood
until birth or even after. After all, the logic applies equally well to dragging
personhood back to day one. Is it that they themselves think their arguments are more apt
to be used in the other direction?
We are dealing with the idea that something as
ultimate as personhood is a matter of personal preference -- a plausible choice among
equally plausible alternatives -- and nothing more. Ordinarily that idea would itself be
an unacceptable cost.
But -- although they may get upset, even angry
-- defenders of abortion are unwilling to back away from arguments whose logic leads to
precisely that end.
For there is an unacceptable cost on the other
side, too. There is an unacceptable cost to recognizing the significance of the power for
reason and choice. That cost is that we would have to recognize that the preborn are
persons. Recognizing that, we would have to stop the killing.