Comments on "Draft
National Institutes of Health Guidelines for Research Involving Human Pluripotent Stem
Cells (December 1999)" -- A written statement of Libertarians for Life, submitted on
behalf of LFL by Doris Gordon, National Coordinator, to the NIH panel on Stem Cell
Guidelines, February 2000
First, I wish to put myself and Libertarians
for Life clearly on the record as objecting to the acquisition of human pluripotent cells
by such illicit means as abortion and donation of "surplus" embryos created by
in vitro fertilization.
Although the Draft Guidelines for Research
Involving Human Pluripotent Stem Cells refers only to the latter means, both means take
the life of the human being who is the source of those pluripotent stem cells; both means
are aggression.
In my comments on the Draft Guidelines,
however, I am going to focus on only four areas that I find particularly disturbing.
Regardless of one's position on abortion or embryo research, these aspects of the Draft
Guidelines have severe problems even within the context of the National Institutes of
Health's (NIH's) own stated positions.
Two of these areas may be seen as substantive
and concerning human embryo research as such; the third and fourth areas may be regarded
as procedural, but I think they have major negative implications for the role played by
the NIH in American society.
I must also note that while the Draft
Guidelines address only human pluripotent stem cells, the current language opens the door
to questions about totipotent cells. Totipotent cells extracted from a human embryo would
appear straightforwardly to be embryos within the meaning of the present Congressional ban
on Federally funded human embryo research. I hope that NIH does not disagree on so
fundamental a matter, but it is certainly raised by the Draft Guidelines and must be
addressed.
The four points I will make are:
A. It is impossible for NIH to disentangle
itself from the destruction of human embryos.
B. The description of "human
pluripotent stem cells" is inadequate, and raises the question of totipotency.
C. There are too many weaknesses in
restrictions on conflict of interest, etc.
D. Accountability is needed.
Although I will address each of the four
general points in greater detail below, my concerns may be summarized as in terms of areas
in the Draft Guidelines as follows:
A. Regarding the interpretation of the
Department of Health and Human Services (DHHS) that NIH is not precluded by current
legislation from engaging in the research envisioned by these Draft Guidelines:
DHHS may interpret the current Congressional
ban on human embryo research using Federal funds as it will. Nonetheless, it is
realistically impossible in fact for the NIH to insulate itself or disentangle itself from
the destruction of embryos that takes place in non-government facilities.
B. Regarding the description of "human
pluripotent stem cells" in I. Scope of Guidelines:
As currently framed, the description is
inadequate. Given changing technologies both of extracting and of manipulating human
pluripotent stem cells, the Draft Guidelines' wording does not necessarily preclude NIH
sponsorship of research it admits itself to be prohibited from funding. Specifically, the
Draft Guidelines' use of the term "potential" is ambiguous. Wording should be
added to make clear that supported efforts cannot — at any stage in the research
— involve the use of cells that have the inherent potential to develop and mature as
a normal human zygote or embryo would. The Guidelines must make it unambiguous that NIH
cannot support research on or creation of cells that are in fact "totipotent".
C. Regarding the practical limitations on
conflicts of interest stated in II. 1. b., on payments in II. 3. e., and on the related
question of whether "donated" stem cells may be transferred out of NIH:
The Draft wording on conflicts of interest and
on payments has serious shortcomings in meeting the Guidelines' stated intents. Those who
would wish NIH to be active here should agree that there must be more separation between
the extraction of any human pluripotent stem cells and the research efforts supported by
NIH. And such a separation must equally apply to the products of such research.
D. Further, there must be clearly understood
accountability and enforcement mechanisms — with teeth — and these should be
stated in the Guidelines document itself.
I. SOME GENERAL OBSERVATIONS
A. Important preliminary distinctions
As I indicated above, the research proposed by
NIH entails the destruction of human embryos — which is illicit per se. Libertarians
For Life cannot support or condone the destruction of human embryos under any
circumstances — whether in the private sector or in government. It is certainly worse
in the case of government, though, because like it or not we are all compelled to support
such activities through taxation.
Were human pluripotent stem cells to be derived
only from embryos who died in spontaneous abortions, or as a byproduct of prenatal surgery
aimed at the benefit of the fetus, I would not object to research per se. (I would, of
course, object to similar research on totipotent cells. Since they have the capacity to
repair themselves when extracted from an embryo, we would be dealing with a human embryo,
not merely a part thereof.)
In articulating my concerns, therefore, I
should also make clear that my comments should not be interpreted as condoning the
research envisioned — even if the Guidelines were changed to respond to the concerns
I will discuss here. The research envisioned necessarily entails the destruction of human
embryos, and that is unjust — regardless of legislation, regardless of the informed
consent of those who donate cells, and regardless of how carefully NIH conducts itself in
supporting research on human pluripotent stem cells.
I hope it is clear here that the suggestions I
make below should not be construed as being able to make NIH's planned activities
acceptable. I hope NIH would make that clear if it chose to respond to them.
The suggestions in the second, third, and
fourth areas would seem to be fully acceptable to NIH within the context of its public
statements. I think these changes to the Draft Guidelines would be in NIH's interests as
an institution. Moreover, I think the manner in which NIH handles this area will be
crucial to how NIH perceives itself and how it is perceived by others.
B. Libertarians for Life's point of view
Interestingly, as a libertarian, I would not
ordinarily be much concerned with the details of NIH policies. I hold, as do virtually all
libertarians, that such scientific research is rightly conducted independently —
outside government and not supported by the inherently coercive mechanism of taxation.
I am concerned with NIH actions here, first,
because I believe that if there is to be any government at all, its primary function is to
defend against aggression, and its unavoidable obligation is not to support or engage in
aggression. Science has demonstrated that we are new human organisms, human offspring,
human beings from fertilization onward. And a realistic philosophy must conclude that we
are persons with the right to be free from aggression, the initiation of force, from that
time also. I necessarily conclude, therefore, that destruction of the zygote/embryo/fetus
is homicide, and doing so deliberately is aggression and violates libertarian principles.
(Libertarians for Life makes a case for immediate personhood and rights from
fertilization. Our reasoning is expressly scientific and philosophical, rather than either
religious or merely pragmatic. For details, you may wish to see the articles on LFL's Web
site: http://www.L4L.org.)
C. NIH's role in society
I recognize that many other libertarians
disagree with me on abortion, just as many nonlibertarians disagree with me and
libertarians in general on whether there should be tax-supported institutions like NIH to
begin with.
I must also note that the current wording of
the Draft Guidelines seems to view NIH's role much more expansively than the facts would
support. In "Supplementary Information," the Draft states, "Federal funding
will provide oversight and direction that would be lacking if this research were the sole
province of private sources of funding...."
On the contrary, whether one supports the
research or opposes it, the scope of NIH's oversight and direction will be limited to
those efforts it actually funds. It may be the case, as the Draft continues, that NIH
funding "will also help ensure that the results of research will be accessible to the
public." But the practical effect of that may well be that research in the private
sector will be subsidized by NIH — not that it will be overseen or directed by
NIH.
In any event, I recognize that the first two
areas I will discuss here raise issues of continuing controversy in American society. As
such, some may argue that NIH can only accept what it regards as the generally accepted
legal framework and support such research and experimentation as it concludes is permitted
by that framework.
But, uniquely in the third and fourth areas, we
are also discussing the role that NIH is perceived as playing in society, and the
confidence that people place in NIH regardless of their political persuasion or their
stand on such issues as abortion or human embryo and fetal experimentation.
In a free society, the underlying factor of
trust and perceived truthfulness may sometimes be more important than whether people agree
or disagree on substantive philosophical or political issues. With that in mind, it is of
particular importance that NIH has recently come under increasing fire from across the
political spectrum, and from those who have no particular political agenda. Serious lapses
have been charged, and some widely documented, in scientific rigor, in institutional
integrity and independence, and even in so rudimentary a matter as informed consent of
persons involved in NIH-supported clinical trials.
I believe it is no longer sufficient for NIH to
ask what line of research is permitted by law. It must ask how such research
is conducted and how it is monitored by NIH. Even with relatively noncontroversial
issues, NIH must ensure strict accountability. This is even more true — as the Draft
Guidelines document itself states — with an issue like stem-cell research.
In this regard, unfortunately, the Draft
Guidelines appear to fall dangerously short of NIH's assurance that it "understands
the ethical, legal, and social issues relevant to human pluripotent stem cell research and
is sensitive to the need to subject it to oversight more stringent than that associated
with the traditional NIH peer review process."
II. DETAILS OF MY CONCERNS
A. It is impossible for NIH to disentangle
itself from the destruction of human embryos.
Regarding DHHS's interpretation of the present
Congressional ban on Federally funded human embryo research:
DHHS has stated that human pluripotent stem
cell research is permitted so long as the government does not itself engage in or support
the act of destroying embryos or fetuses in order to secure the human pluripotent stem
cells:
"Federal law currently prohibits DHHS from
funding research in which human embryos are created for research purposes or are
destroyed, discarded or subjected to greater than minimal risk. ... DHHS concluded that
the Congressional prohibition does not prohibit the funding of research utilizing human
pluripotent stem cells because such cells are not embryos." (Draft Guidelines,
Supplementary Information)
I would say that the DHHS interpretation runs
counter to the clear intent of the law. (In which regard, it is disturbing that the
interpretation, at least as reported in the Draft Guidelines document, is silent on the
use of human totipotent stem cells.) However, we must also ask whether it is possible
for NIH to conduct itself in the manner that would be required by DHHS's own
interpretation.
To be sure, NIH-funded researchers will not be
extracting the cells. Also, proponents of the activity will argue that NIH will not be
billed for such activity per se, but merely for expenses incurred. But the question is
whether a significant amount of that activity will take place only because NIH
efforts will accept the "product" thereof, the human pluripotent stem cells
— and will allow those who perform the activity to recoup a significant amount,
perhaps all, of the costs of "producing" that "product."
If NIH Guidelines were to require that
researchers accept only human pluripotent stem cells given strictly free of charge, how
many would be given? Some, to be sure; but I think it highly unlikely that the number
would be sufficient to support the research NIH envisions.
NIH and its supported efforts, then, are not
merely "accepting" such cells. Rather, they are establishing a nexus of
expectations, implied mutual obligations, and remuneration whose purpose — arguably,
whose only purpose — is to produce such cells. In effect, NIH is saying
that while it is prohibited from performing the action itself, it can essentially
"subcontract" it.
I find such an argument unpersuasive.
Inevitably, NIH is actively encouraging the creation of "excess" human embryos.
Conceding that DHHS's interpretation might
nevertheless carry, however, we must still ask whether the Draft Guidelines adequately
protect against activities that DHHS itself regards as forbidden. And I would say that
they fail that test.
B. The description of "human
pluripotent stem cells" is inadequate, and raises the question of totipotency.
The description of human pluripotent stem cells
occurs in Section I. There, "human pluripotent stem cells" are described as
"cells derived from human embryos or fetal tissue that can divide for indefinite
periods in culture without specializing and have the potential to develop into all of the
three major tissue types."
1. Different kinds of cells
In order to meet the conditions expressed
elsewhere in the Supplementary Information and in the legislation cited, the Guidelines
would have to add words to make explicit that no such cells have the inherent
potential to develop and mature as a normal human embryo would. And by this, I do not mean
that researchers ought not to permit such development; I am concerned specifically
with whether such cells have the capacity to so develop — even if lethally
impaired, for instance, by an inability to produce a placenta.
Further, the wording should indicate that
supported research may not so alter the stem cells that they would have the capacity to
develop as a normal zygote or embryo would, even though they were prevented from
exercising that capacity.
Please note that I am concerned here with two
situations independently: first, with stem cells that may be received by an NIH-supported
research effort; thereafter, with any alteration that may occur during such research.
2. The ambiguity in "potential"
Frankly, I initially found the description of
human pluripotent stem cells to be either self-contradictory or in need of considerable
amplification. How, I asked, can the cells be said both to have a "potential"
but continue "indefinitely" without expressing it?
Obviously, much hinges on the meaning of the
word "potential." This is a term that NIH must carefully and honestly define in
a realistic manner. Partially, this can be addressed by making clear that human totipotent
stem cells are not permitted as the subjects of NIH-supported research.
However, the term "potential" must
still be clarified on its own. Does it simply refer to the sense in which we would refer
to the zygote as having the potential for further growth and development into its later
stages as embryo, fetus, and infant, etc.? That is, in this normal sense of the term
"potential," the zygote mainly requires a suitable environment and appropriate
biochemical signals made available in that environment in order to simply grow and develop
further as a human being. Or are the Draft Guidelines also using "potential" in
the sense that one might, for instance, talk of somatic or germ cells at some stage in a
cloning process — where experimenters can change a cell itself "back into"
a zygote?
While it is true that human pluripotent stem
cells cannot — left to themselves — develop into an embryo, even lethally
impaired, it is also true that current technology can already so alter a pluripotent or
even a highly differentiated somatic cell so as to return it to the zygote stage. And
future technology could provide the means for even further genetic manipulation of such
cells.
Will still newer technologies provide NIH with
cells that can still be called "human pluripotent stem cells" within the Draft
Guidelines' current description, but which will have the potential to develop along the
lines of a normal embryo, and whose development must be actively inhibited in order
to stay within the Guidelines' description?
I can hardly project the course of future
technology. More to the point, however, I do not think that very many others can either.
3. Alteration by researchers
We do not need to move outside the realm of
current technology, however, in order to be concerned about the manipulation of human
pluripotent stem cells after they have been received by a research project. We must
already deal with the reality of Dolly, and any number of other cloned animals that have
been already successfully produced from differentiated somatic and germ line cells. The
use of human pluripotent stem cells to produce a new human embryo is clearly
technologically near — if not a fait accompli. So long as normal development were
restrained, such an alteration would not seem to be precluded by the Draft Guidelines'
current wording.
The Draft Guideline's current wording (in III.
Areas of Research Involving Human Pluripotent Stem Cells that are Ineligible for NIH
Funding) does note research goals that cannot be supported (such as the production of
chimeras, etc.). But the current wording does not set boundaries on how the
potential of the stem cells may affect the permissibility of research on them (again, not
even to the extent of stipulating that the use of totipotent cells is not permitted).
Precisely because of DHHS's own legal
reasoning, I believe that the Guidelines' language must make absolutely clear the possible
boundaries of future developments in which NIH cannot take part — not merely
with regard to the goals of research, but also with regard to the subject of the
research, the nature and capacities — normal or altered — of the stem cells
themselves.
4. Some possible responses
It may be argued that distinctions in the
meanings of "potential" are an excessively abstract or philosophical realm for
NIH to concern itself with.
Nonetheless, such distinctions can be expressed
in operational terms that should pose no difficulty of understanding for the research
community and the public at large.
It may further be responded that concerns about
the nature of the cells would fall within the purview of the Human Pluripotent Stem Cell
Review Group (HPSCRG) and its review of any "newly derived line of human pluripotent
stem cells that has not been reviewed previously."
But the HPSCRG itself needs guidance. A strict
reading of the current wording of the Draft Guidelines would seem to permit NIH
researchers to alter pluripotent cells so that they become totipotent — so long as
the researcher prevents the cells from developing as a normal embryo would.
The current wording speaks primarily of what
the stem cells will not do; it does not speak of what they could do.
5. A critical distinction
From a libertarian pro-life perspective, the
critical distinction in principle is whether or not a particular cell or group of
cells are merely parts of an embryo, and will remain such. The critical practical
question is whether these parts or cells can be manipulated in such a way as to return
them to a state where they would have the same inherent capacities as a naturally
occurring zygote or embryo — which embryo could then be allowed to develop further as
a human being.
If the cell or group of cells has the inherent
capacity to act like a normal zygote or embryo, then it is already a zygote or
embryo.
At some point, the cells that became Dolly
started to act as a normal sheep embryo. The fact that this point was reached through an
artificial process is irrelevant to the fact that there was now a new, complete, whole
biological individual. The same principle holds true with human cells — even if
development is permanently inhibited or is terminated by the researchers.
Either way, the obvious issue is whether we are
dealing with the killing of a human being. If the cell or group of cells can never behave
in the manner of a zygote or embryo, or must themselves be altered to do so, then —
to make the distinction in bluntly pro-life language — destroying them is not
homicide or aggression. But, even in this case, a homicide would still have occurred in
the "subcontractor's" laboratory, although not in the stem-cell researcher's
lab.
However, if technology provides NIH-supported
researchers with a human "pluripotent" stem cell that can behave like a zygote
or embryo, and must be inhibited from doing so, then there would be homicides in both
cases: those in the "subcontractors'" laboratories; and those in the NIH-funded
laboratories. Similarly, there would be two homicides if a stem cell (or group) were
returned to the state of a zygote or early embryo.
Obviously, I recognize that many would insist
such destruction would in no way be homicides. Regardless, in these latter events human
embryos would have been destroyed, and NIH would be unambiguously complicit and in
violation of the law.
6. The nature of the cells
In the case of human pluripotent stem cells
received by researchers from outside NIH, it may be argued by some that the
"two-homicide" case is not technologically possible at the moment. Regarding
research on such stem cells, however, alteration is all too easy.
Therefore, the question here is whether NIH is
indeed "sensitive to the need to subject [this research] to oversight more stringent
than that associated with the traditional NIH peer review process." To that extent, I
believe it would be well to make thoroughly explicit what NIH will not accept for
research in the future.
Again, it is not merely that the use of the
word "potential" with regard to human pluripotent stem cells is open to
differences in interpretation, or that the Guidelines' wording may be overtaken by changes
in technology. The nature of human pluripotent stem cell itself is already close to
the edge of what we mean by a zygote or embryo.
A human pluripotent stem cell or group of such
cells may not have the "potential" to develop as a normal zygote or embryo would
develop. But such cells are remarkably receptive to alteration such that they would
so develop. Considering both policy, and the nature of the entities being studied, the
Guidelines should not be susceptible to ambiguity on the nature of the cells to be studied
and on alterations that would not be permitted.
Others would be better qualified than I to
suggest appropriate wording, but I do find that the Draft Guidelines need amplification in
this area. This, however, is merely one case in which the Guidelines will serve as an
indication of how seriously NIH takes the assurances those Guidelines would offer the
public. The third area in which I am concerned is much more concrete.
C. There are too many weaknesses in
restrictions on conflict of interest, etc.
1. Conflicts of interest
In II. 1. b., it is stated that, "To avoid
possible conflicts of interest, the attending physician responsible for the fertility
treatment and the researcher or investigator deriving and/or proposing to utilize human
pluripotent stem cells should not have been one and the same person."
Realistically, it would seem necessary to add
that such persons should not have any continuing business or research association. It is
precisely the point of "conflict of interest" that it is not limited to
individuals but is critically important in an organizational and business sense.
2. Payments
In II. 3. e., it is stated that an
investigator's application should provide "an assurance that stem cells to be used in
the research were or will be obtained through a donation or through a payment that does
not exceed the reasonable costs associated with transportation, processing, preservation,
quality control and storage of the stem cells."
Unfortunately, the scope of costs permitted to
be incurred is sufficiently wide that it appears all to easy for an organization or
enterprise to establish a significant revenue source in the activities described. The
potential for abuse or simple misinterpretation of "reasonable costs" is
sufficiently strong that the Guidelines themselves should give strong and clear indication
of the boundaries of such costs.
Additionally, the wording of the limitation
appears to refer primarily to the initiation of an effort. It is a statement of intent,
with no discussion of whether or how that intent will be verified.
The Guidelines should make clear that the
activities permitted for cost coverage should be not such that they can establish
themselves as part of an organization's economic expectations or viability; moreover, the
organization should not be able to subcontract the activities in such a way that the
subcontractor would be able to conduct the activities as a profit-making venture. Further,
the Guidelines should indicate that NIH will expect reasonable evidence of this, both
before and after the activities take place.
3. Transfers of stem cells
Also, the Draft Guidelines do not articulate in
any manner whether NIH may or may not transfer "donated" stem cells outside NIH
— either in their normal state, or in any altered state — and whether such
transfer may be made to other Federal government departments or offices, or to
researchers, labs, or organizations outside the Federal government. To the extent NIH is
serious about its assurances, it should add clear and unambiguous language to the
Guidelines indicating whether such transfers are permitted and if so, under what
conditions.
Such transfers would seem of dubious propriety,
at best. The Draft Guidelines already allow the possibility of NIH establishing a
continuing economic nexus supporting the destruction of human embryos; to permit transfers
of stem cells after NIH-supported activities would establish NIH as a conduit to subsidize
these activities in commercial and other nongovernmental research.
D. Accountability is needed.
And in all these issues, as I said at the
beginning, there must be clearly stated accountability and enforcement mechanisms —
with teeth.
It may be responded that other NIH policies
already provide the needed mechanisms, that describing them here would be redundant.
Nonetheless, given the gravity of the issues involved, I believe the principles involved
should be clearly restated here. If that is redundant, redundancy is no disadvantage. (It
might even assist in a wider review of NIH policies.)
Unfortunately, parts of the Draft Guidelines
highlight the fact that wording alone is insufficient. In II. 2., the Draft Guidelines
indicate the need for informed consent. This is hardly a matter of controversy. But it is
in precisely this noncontroversial area that NIH has come under fire in recent months. It
is not that there was anything particularly wrong with NIH's policy statements and
regulations on informed consent for human subjects. The problem is that they were not followed.
The problem is that research was not adequately monitored.
The principle of accountability must
certainly be unmistakable in the Guidelines. However, no matter how well the Guidelines
are formulated, there must be follow through; there must be monitoring; there must be
clearly understood and enforced sanctions for noncompliance.
Any limitations on the nature of the cells to
be worked on must be observed both before research begins, and thereafter. NIH must follow
through in a manner that is clearly understood, predictable in advance, and conducted
without any attempt to gloss over or ignore unpleasant facts. "Business as
usual" seems no longer to be an option for NIH, particularly in regard to an issue
like human pluripotent stem cell research.
III. IN CLOSING
It is unlikely that we are going to come to a
quick agreement on the underlying controversies, nor is it realistic to think that NIH
would be a major instrument of such a process. But how NIH conducts itself will have a
major impact on how research is perceived in general, and on how NIH is perceived in
particular.
As I have said above, even if NIH were to
attempt to accept as many of my comments as possible, I would still find research in this
area to be unacceptable. Human embryos, who are human beings, persons with rights, must
necessarily be destroyed in order for the research to take place.
I must admit, therefore, that I find myself in
an unusual position here. As you may know, a majority of libertarians support choice on
abortion, and many emphatically support embryo research. Nonetheless, the cynical among
libertarians have indicated no surprise at all at recent reports of problems in NIH's
handling of human subjects. Similarly, people that I regard to be quite liberal have
proven to be equally jaundiced with regard to NIH.
Some of them have told me that I should not
care whether NIH conducts itself in a way that undermines its own legitimacy. In fact,
they would welcome that.
Given the stakes, I hope NIH disagrees with
them on this — and proves them wrong.