My name is Doris Gordon. I have been a libertarian since 1959. Originally, I supported
abortion choice. Now, I am the national coordinator of Libertarians for Life, which I
founded. Libertarians for Life's reasoning is based on science and philosophy rather than
religion. Personally, I am an atheist and a Jew.
Abortion raises two critical questions: the moral status
of prenatal human beings, and the pregnant woman's right to control her own body.
Conceiving children outside their mother's body and storing them frozen has one virtue:
these cases give visible evidence that the moral status and the rights of a prenatal child
are independent of the mother's status and rights. The body to be subjected to involuntary
experimentation is not the mother's body.
There are good scientific and philosophical
reasons to say that I began my life when I was conceived. There is not even one good
reason that shows otherwise. Being libertarian, I insist upon the right to control my own
body. When I was a zygote, it was my body and nobody else's. The ethical objection to
human embryo research is that such research presumes the embryo is not an actual human
being but something else. But it was no vegetable, no mere animal, no pre-human, no piece
of property from whom I received my life; my mother and my father gave me life directly.
Unfortunately, using an embryonic human being as a guinea pig tramples on the right of
that human being to her own body.
Let's turn to your list of "Major Policy
Questions" and focus on Questions 1 and 2; the other three are subsidiary questions.
Question 1 asks, "What are the competing ethical frameworks with respect to the moral
status of the embryo?"
One framework is that all human beings are
persons, from conception to death. This framework accords with the libertarian claim that
life and rights are inseparable. The opposing framework is that there are two tiers of
human offspring: a superior class of persons with rights, and a sub-human class of
non-persons without legal protection. A two-tiered view of humanity sees life as separable
from rights. The premise underlying human embryo research is two tiers of humanity. This
premise offers no obstacle to slavery, treating women as chattel, the Holocaust, and
innumerable other cases of aggression.
Question 2 asks, "If the embryo in some
sense deserves respect, what is owed and at what stages in development? This
question," you added, "should touch on the 14-day limit issue and be informed by
available scientific information."
First, regarding what is owed, all persons owe
all other persons to not aggress against them. Parents owe their children support and
protection from harm because they owe their children non-aggression. Parents who kill
their children by abortion or who donate them to science are violating their obligation
not to aggress.
Regarding the 14-day limit, there is no barrier
in Roe v. Wade against lifting this limit and raising it higher and still higher.
Unfortunately, Roe dodged the essential nature of the child and made the child's
location pivotal. But there's nothing magical about being outside a place as opposed to
being inside. What if one day prenatal children might be put into artificial wombs where
they could live and grow indefinitely? This panel has to ask about a 14-day limit because
even many abortion choicers worry about the fact that any line-drawing other than at
conception is merely subjective and arbitrary.
When my children were toddlers, we read a
sex-education book that told the truth. It said, "At the beginning of you, you were
no bigger than a dot -- a tiny dot, much smaller even than the dot on this page."1
"The little egg in your mother's body, by itself, was
not you. And the little sperm in your father's body, by itself wasn't you. You began to be
only when the two joined together. That was the moment you started to be yourself. That
was the moment when you became able to grow into a baby, and after that into a boy or
girl, and after that into a man or woman."2 A future
book ought to warn toddlers, if you become a human embryologist, what you see under the
microscope might be your own frozen brother, sister, cousin, aunt, or uncle.
Let's imagine you could watch a "Back to
the Future" scenario in which you, yourself, are the frozen embryo. If someone was
going to experiment on you, would you have good reason to object?
I would.3
Footnotes:
- Sidonie Matsner Gruenberg, The Wonderful Story
of How You Were Born, p. 4, Doubleday & Company, Inc., 1959.
- Ibid, p. 24
- For a libertarian defense of the rights of
prenatal human beings, please read "Why Abortion Violates Rights," by Doris
Gordon, which I have submitted for inclusion in the record. Its arguments are relevant to
human embryo research as well as abortion.