But there's an obvious difference here.
However we describe parental obligation, one essential factor of it is that the act of
conception is voluntary for the parents, not for the child. In the case of pregnancy due
to rape, it is voluntary for neither the child nor the mother.
Pregnancy due to rape acts against the woman's
liberty. In some sense, it's a perpetuation of the aggression of the rapist. Regardless of
the practical problems of pregnancy, rape is a major trauma, and the pregnancy complicates
that still further.
Not yet a technological way out
At least right now, moreover, pregnancy due to
rape is not a case where we can "negotiate" a practical, win-win solution --
where the woman is free of any burden to care for the child, and where the child's life is
saved.
Perhaps technology will be able to offer a
practical solution in the future. Safe adoption is permissible in the normal case of
parenthood; it is certainly permissible in the case of pregnancy due to rape. With
advances in technology, "prenatal adoption" may turn out no different from any
other adoption.
That will be a way to avoid our
practical dilemma. Until then, we have to confront it.
What do we do when aggression places us in such
a situation?
Analogies
I'm not crazy about analogies, but some people
like them, and I can think of a few.
Let's imagine first a case where you are in the
position of the fetus. You are knocked out and kidnapped; your captor hides you on the
plane of an innocent third party. She, the unfortunate pilot, doesn't discover you until
you come to at 10,000 feet. Your presence has been forced on her without her knowledge or
consent. She states plainly that you don't have any right to be there, and she wants you
out. Do you have the obligation to jump out? Or to let her push you out? Or does she have
the obligation to land in a safe place before she makes you leave?
In a more complex one, you are on a mountain,
and I attack you and throw you into a place filled with rocks that will tumble down below
if given a push. The only way you can leave that spot is by causing a landslide. On a
perch below is someone else I also forced there. If there's a landslide, their perch will
be destroyed and they'll fall to their death. There is no way for your calls for help to
be heard; you have to wait until you are discovered missing and a rescue party is sent.
Let's assume that you are in no danger; one of your hobbies is to be a survivalist; you
know how to attract game birds. You are able to live off them until found, but that will
take nine months. The other person is also able to survive because your efforts to attract
birds will inevitably attract birds to their perch, too.
Does your right to liberty include a right to
push the rocks out of the way and cause the death of the other person?
The libertarian principle is, if A harms B,
that does not entitle B to harm C. Both the pilot and the rape victim still retain the
normal obligation not to intervene in an ongoing situation so as to cause an innocent
person to die. If the child dies due to the woman's intervention, she, not the rapist, is
the proximate cause of the child's death.
And let it be noted that there is a problem
even in cases where continued positive effort is called for in order to avoid causing
harm. Let's say I lock you in place with a gun in your hand; the hammer is cocked, held
back by your thumb. If you ease the pressure, it fires and kills someone else also locked
in place. Do you have the right to ease the pressure?
In another case, I've put you with your hand on
a button. If you ease the pressure there, you cut off the current that is powering an
elevator's safe descent: the elevator will then just drop, almost certainly killing
those within.
In the one case, your effort is needed to
maintain a set of normal, safe conditions; in the other, to prevent unleashing an explicit
attack. Either way, withdrawal of such effort would implement an aggression.
There are obviously boundaries to such issues.
Can you keep your hand firmly on a button or a trigger indefinitely? Obviously not. If you
were about to be killed by someone else, would you have the obligation under justice to
stay in place and let yourself be murdered? Hardly. But it seems in at least some cases we
may be obligated to tolerate some injustice to ourselves in order to avoid committing
injustice to others.
But before pursuing that further, what if we
say the woman does have a right in principle to remove (evict) the fetus regardless
of the consequences?
Acting as the rapist's "agent"
Libertarians would generally agree that we have
no pre-existing obligation to meet the needs of others (absent contract, having committed
aggression, etc.). LFL's argument in favor of parental obligation reflects the fact that
parents cause the needs of their children by voluntarily causing the children to exist in
a state of dependence. The lack of such voluntary causation is why, above, I conceded that
the mother who conceived due to rape does not have the normal obligation parents have to
their children.
So, it would appear as if she could
simply cut off the sustenance her body is providing, remove the child, and that's that.
It is not, however, so simple: If she
has no parental obligation to the child, that's not true of the father, the rapist. His
parental obligation is intact. He has the obligation to provide care and protection to the
child, just as any ordinary parent. However, in effect, he has been grossly negligent to
the child. It's just as if parents had forced their child on someone, who would therefore
almost certainly be unwilling to take care of the child.
In the case of rape, the father has placed the
child totally and utterly within the power of the mother. He has committed an immediate
act of aggression against the woman. But to the extent the woman's actions harm their
child, to that extent the rapist has also aggressed against the child.
The woman herself does not have the normal
parental obligation to provide for her child -- although she still has the universal
obligation not to aggress against the child. She obviously has no right to deliberately
kill the kid; but also, she may not act as someone else's agent of aggression.
The problem is that in withdrawing the
sustenance, by simple removal, she acts as the agent of the negligent father. She
exercises the power the father has given her. Her withdrawal of sustenance will render him
guilty of an explicit act of aggression against the child. She brings it about.
For the mother to cut off sustenance, she must
actively intervene in the situation. Unlike someone who sees a kid deposited on the
church steps, she is not able merely to sit on her hands. Under libertarian principles,
she would have the right to sit on her hands; but in order to cut off sustenance, she
actually has to go in there and intervene in the biological process. Even though cutting
off sustenance can be rationalized as passive, it is in fact active. And she is executing
the power thrust upon her by the father; she is actively behaving as the agent of his
aggression. She doesn't have the right to do that; no one does.
Trapped between aggressions
The dilemma for both her and the rest of us
arises from the fact that she is cornered between two acts of aggression. If she
continues to carry the child, to some extent she perpetuates the aggression of the father
against herself. If she cuts off sustenance, she initiates the father's aggression against
the child.
How do we deal with this?
One principle to keep in mind is that it is
less evil to suffer injustice than to commit injustice. And we can also note that the evil
of the forcible provision of sustenance is less than the evil of causing the child's
death.
Both of those responses, however, are addressed
to the woman. What about the rest of us?
If the woman decides to withdraw the
sustenance, is anyone going to do anything about it? Bystanders have the right,
presumably, to act in defense of the rights of a victim of aggression. But this is not a
simple case of a parent (the father, the rapist) endangering a child. This is a case where
the parent in question is also committing an on-going aggression against the other parent,
the woman.
For us to intervene, then, is not simply to
intervene against the aggression against the child. Necessarily, our intervention to
protect the child would also have the consequence of perpetuating one element of the
father's aggression against the mother, the woman.
So where does this leave bystanders, those who
would act in the child's defense?
For the bystanders, one question will be, which
is the greater aggression? We, too, like the mother, are confronted with a choice between
injustices. Assuming that her pregnancy has not turned life threatening, etc., the facts
seem to be that causing the death of the child would be the greater aggression.
Important differences
In all this, it sounds as if the raped
woman has the same obligations as parents who conceive voluntarily. She presumably has to
carry the kid to term -- just like the mother in the normal case. While it is true that
the kid can be adopted, voluntary parents can put kids up for adoption, too.
What then are the differences?
First, we must at least make one point about our
relation to the problem: While it seems that we do have the right to defend the child, the
mixed nature of this situation means that by doing so, we would incur obligations
to the mother. In other words, someone who would intervene to save the life of the
child is also obligated to provide means of support for the woman, so as to ameliorate to
whatever extent possible the presence of the father's continuing injustice against the
woman.
That's not the case in intervening to prevent
someone from skipping out on a debt. That's not the case in intervening to prevent parents
from dropping their kids in the woods.
Next, adoption is not entirely
"optional" for normal parents. They have the right to seek others who
wish to care for their children. But if they fail, they've still got the
obligation.
The rape victim, however, is restrained only
insofar as she is acting as the agent of the father. She is his agent only in so
far as she is uniquely empowered by the father.
Obviously, when the child is born, she loses
all uniqueness; if by doing nothing she effects an injustice by the father against the
child, then so does everyone else! The earlier that others can step in without
endangering the child, then the earlier she loses her unique empowerment by the father,
the earlier she is no longer acting as his agent. If she is obligated, so is everyone
else; and we cannot force others to fulfill our obligations.
The underlying threat to the victims
Finally, it must be noted that one element in
the woman's desire to be rid of the child has nothing to do with either her, the child, or
even the rapist. The victim of rape is frequently seen by those around her as if she
were the criminal.
It's the double victimization of rape. In many
segments of society, for the woman to carry the child to term is to admit
"guilt". The same forces that dismiss the significance of rape also demand
abortion as a precondition of recognizing any wrong done to the woman: if she doesn't want
the kid dead, if she's not willing actually to kill the kid, then she wasn't
"really" raped.
Children born of rape, also, are frequently
treated as if they were the guilty ones.
Such social victimization is, at least, one
point that all of us, regardless of our positions on abortion, should recognize as a
threat -- against the woman, against the child, against what it means to be a person with
rights.